|
|
RANDOM THOUGHTS ON SCHABAS-STANTON-JOHANSEN
Searching for the truth. Number
25. January 2002.
Magazine of Documentation Center
of Cambodia (Khmer version).
By Suzannah Linton
The debates about jurisdiction over genocide are ‘academic’
and irrelevant
I do not agree. The issue of jurisdiction is highly
relevant, and is properly to be determined by the Extraordinary Chambers.
One of the reasons why it is so important is the fundamental principle of
criminal justice that prohibits someone from being convicted of something that
was not a crime under the relevant law at the time it was committed. This is a
particular issue in judicial processes that attempt to bring justice to
historical atrocities as the legal situation is confused and does need to be
clarified if there is to be a fair process.
The preceding debates on whether the Genocide Convention
applies in Cambodia or not are between someone taking an objective view, reading
the law as it is and testing what happened in Cambodia against that and someone
who attempts to make the situation fit into the law or vice versa. Both
are well-intentioned and I sympathise. However, I do believe the
principled objective approach taken by Professor Schabas is the correct
one. If that is what the law said
at the time the acts were perpetrated, we are stuck with it. Attempts at clever lawyering become
artificial even dishonest after a while.
The convention has obvious cracks and the Khmer Rouge practice of killing
off their own people, called auto-genocide by some, has indeed hit a ‘blind
spot’. I would have liked to see
this discussion underpinned by a more constructive examination of the reasons
why the drafters excluded certain groups from protection and whether we need to
consider changes to the Genocide Convention in light of its inherent
limitations.
One of the writers seems to assume that the selection of
the subject matter jurisdiction for the KR tribunal (genocide, crimes against
humanity etc) means a decision has been taken that these things happened in
Cambodia and it is just a matter of deciding if the accused did what he is
accused of. I disagree, even though I recognise that the drafters do
impose a certain understanding of the situation upon the court (eg. by limiting
war crimes to grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions they appear to have
decided there was an international armed conflict). The accused may still
challenge the jurisdiction, for example on the ground that at the time of the
offence, such an act was not a crime and not prosecutable. The role of the
court is to decide, on the basis of evidence submitted by the parties, whether
the wider as well as the specific elements are satisfied. For example when
looking at the grave breach provisions, it will have to decide whether 1. There
was an armed conflict 2. That armed was international 3. Whether the Geneva Conventions applied
4. Whether the legal elements of a grave breach are satisfied (victim was
protected person or property, accused sufficiently linked to a party to the
conflict etc). Likewise, the prosecution will have to prove genocide
happened in Cambodia and then, and that an accused’s acts were genocidal.
The origins of the notion of genocide and
crimes against humanity
I agree that the nexus to an armed conflict in the crimes
against humanity definition in the IMT Charter was artificial. Without the
link to an armed conflict (when the laws of war would apply and on which there
was less controversy), many of the crimes committed in the Second World War
would have been considered to be within the domestic jurisdiction of the German
Reich and nobody else’s business. As it was, the charges on the Holocaust
were a minor part of the case against the leadership at the Nuremburg
International Military Tribunal. The link to the armed conflict made it
the business of other States and thus enabled the crimes to be prosecuted by
States who would otherwise be violating that cardinal principle of domestic
sovereignty. It has long been acknowledged that this nexus between crimes
against humanity and either crimes against peace or war crimes, was peculiar to
the jurisdiction of the Nuremberg Tribunal. It disappeared from the definition
contained in Article II(1)(c) of Control Council Law No. 10 and has come to be
abandoned in customary international law (the ICTY Statute’s definition of
crimes against humanity is recognized, even in its own jurisprudence, as being
out of line with custom).
If one sees genocide as a species of crime against
humanity, it is not irrelevant that back in 1948 already, the crime was not seen
as having a nexus to an armed conflict. It would seem that by 1975
the nexus was not a characteristic of the crime against humanity in customary
international law, as evidenced by State practice and opinio juris. But
Professor Schabas is right in that somewhere between 1945 and 1993, the nexus
disappeared. It will be for the Extraordinary Chambers to decide whether it was
still a legal element of the crime against humanity in the period 1975 –
1979. So there seems to me to be no point in getting too hung up about
this or the reason why the nexus was present in the IMT Charter.
Technically, genocide as a legal prohibition only came into
existence in International Law with the Genocide Convention and was first
successfully prosecuted in an international tribunal at the International
Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (Akayesu). Its definition was settled at a
time before the Cold War hardened positions and when the world was still
struggling to comprehend the enormity of Nazi atrocities and determined to
prevent its recurrence. Genocide is founded in the concept of the killing
of a people, what occurred during the Holocaust. One has to be careful
with linking genocide too tightly to the IMT Charter and Judgement although it
clearly has its roots in the notion of the crime against humanity and the
evolution of criminal responsibility for acts of extreme brutality committed in
armed conflict. I wouldn’t call the Convention definition political, but
rather one that arose directly from the experiences of the war and reflected the
realities of the time. What we should be looking at is whether the time is
right to reconsider the convention.
International Criminal Law is usurping the
jurisdiction of domestic courts
Underlying the arguments here seems to be a belief that the
International Community is falling over itself to ‘steal’ the jurisdiction of
domestic courts. Not so. The sorry record of post-Nuremburg justice
reveals a reality of indifference and failure to act even in the face of the
most egregious crimes. Only two ad-hoc international criminal tribunals
have been created by the Security Council, and both acknowledge the role of
domestic courts even if they have precedence should they choose to exercise
jurisdiction. Neither the ICTY nor ICTR have precluded domestic trials
under domestic law – in Bosnia there is a scheme called ‘Rules of the Road’
whereby the Prosecutors office approves cases for domestic trial (the Bosnian
Penal Code recognises war crimes etc). Rwanda’s prisons are notoriously
packed with persons awaiting trial in domestic courts. There is to date
just one functioning hybrid ‘internationalised domestic tribunal’, that of East
Timor, and it is located in the District Court of Dili. The ICC is
structured on the concept of complementarity: domestic courts are the first port
of call. If those courts are unable or unwilling to fulfill their
international obligations, and subject to the terms of the Statute, the ICC is
able to exercise its jurisdiction.
I think the September 11 attacks are what has really
motivated Raymund’s article. Calls for such serious crimes to be dealt with in
an international arena will always be stronger when there is concern about the
inability or unwillingness of the State to fulfill its legal responsibilities in
domestic law. No one is denying that the US has jurisdiction and the right
to try those involved in the horrendous attacks. But, irrespective of the
high quality of its courts and judges, there needs to be some understanding of
what the wider world is thinking and why even objective observers could be
inclined towards some form of international tribunal for Bin Laden and his
associates. America and so many of
its institutions have demonised the man and as a result he has been convicted in
the public mind. Many Moslem
nations are convinced that America is persecuting Moslems and will take revenge
by punishing those Afghanis who simply defended their country from attack.
One need only switch on CNN and listen to its journalists, American leaders and
the public at large to get a sense of why some may feel there could be genuine
problems of fair trial in the USA.
Are genocide and crimes against humanity more
serious than domestic crimes?
I agree that that mass murder is and will always be a
violation of domestic law. That is why domestic law is in the Law on
Extraordinary Chambers; it is also there as recognition of national sovereignty,
and to act as a ‘fall-back’ should the prosecution not be able to prove
international crimes. But the question is whether some crimes are so awful
that they are considered as a separate class of crime and can fall to be tried
by States or international judicial bodies.
One contributor finds the notion that crimes against
humanity and genocide are more serious than domestic crimes to be
offensive. He suggests that it is legal experts and the like who have
arbitrarily come up with the notion that some crimes are more serious than
others. There has for a very long time existed a notion that certain
crimes are so shocking to the conscience of mankind as to transcend the
traditional boundaries of State sovereignty and engage the responsibilities of
the entire international community. There are plenty of examples to
evidence this. Humanitarian intervention arose as a response to gross
violations of human rights committed in the Christian lands occupied by the
Ottomans, and State sovereignty was subordinated, if temporarily. After
WWI, there were attempts at crimes against humanity prosecutions in Turkey for
the massacres of Armenians, but these were eventually abandoned. There
were the post World War II cases, in particular the International Military
Tribunal at Nuremburg prosecuting for crimes against peace, war crimes and
crimes against humanity. The Genocide Convention and Geneva Conventions of
1949 came later. There should be no doubt that it is International Law,
borne out in the practice of States and opinio juris, that regards certain
crimes as particularly serious and deserving of the attention of the
international community, and not the arbitrary Ivory Tower musings of certain
academics.
So, what is an international crime? A crime that is
so serious that it goes beyond an ordinary domestic crime. It is usually subject to a legal
definition set out in customary international law or treaty – terrorism is
admittedly a crime with no common agreed definition, for as has been repeated
many a time, one man’s terrorist is another man’s freedom fighter.
International crimes are so serious as to trigger certain legal consequences for
States. One of those is universal jurisdiction. When international
crimes such as genocide, crimes against humanity and war crimes are perpetrated,
all States (including the State where the crime happened) are obliged to
investigate, prosecute and punish suspects within their jurisdiction in relation
to that crime or extradite such persons to another State to stand trial.
An aggressive interpretation of this basic concept allows States keen to ‘do
their part’ by actually hunting down suspects in countries that aren’t doing
anything. The person accused of an international crime can be arrested and
prosecuted by any State; in fact, there is a legal obligation upon States
to take action. This does not occur for ordinary murder, even mass murder,
which is premised on the understanding that the accused will be tried in the
State with jurisdiction, and getting hold of the accused will be governed
by rules on inter-state cooperation in crime prevention and extradition
laws. The situation is now complicated by international legal bodies such
as ad-hoc criminal tribunals to which one cannot extradite, but can simply
‘transfer’ someone to stand trial. Be that as it may, it should be clear
that these bodies do not exclude the exercise of jurisdiction by national
courts.
It is not true that international justice means that we are
moving towards an international adjudication of crimes and will do away with
domestic jurisdiction. It means
that States have to comply with their obligations to each other to contribute to
the maintenance of international peace and security by using their domestic law
to repress these very serious crimes. The international judicial
bodies come into the picture because of an inability or unwillingness on the
part of the State to meet its obligations. As for the suggestion that
international crimes were never meant to be prosecuted in domestic courts, I
would draw the writer’s attention to the provisions in the four Geneva
Conventions of 1949 about how States Parties are required to adapt their laws to
permit the proper implementation of the enforcement mechanisms – and prosecution
is a key tool for ensuring respect for International Humanitarian Law.
Also, I would point out that genocide, crimes against humanity, torture and war
crimes are increasingly being prosecuted in domestic courts – for example,
Balkan war crimes suspects have been prosecuted not just in the Balkans, but
also in domestic courts in Switzerland, Norway, Germany and The Netherlands,
just to name a few. The Spanish are famously after General Pinochet; the
Belgians have prosecuted suspected genocidaires from Rwanda and are now after
Ariel Sharon for the Shabra and Shatila massacres. I would also stress
that domestic law was applied in the occupied zones of Germany - the Canadians
used Canadian law and the Brits used the Royal Warrant of 1945 with attached
regulations (Control Council Law No. 10 used in the US zone followed the IMT
Charter in the main). German courts applied German law to try German war
criminals. The Israelis used a domestic law to try the kidnapped Adolf
Eichmann.
The hierarchy of international
crimes
This is a touchy subject. Some see a hierarchy that
begins with aggression, going down to genocide, crimes against humanity and then
war crimes. Others say it is immoral to enter into a process that looks at
how many victims and the degree of suffering caused and creating first and
second class crimes. Some say this notion of a hierarchy is just not
borne out by international jurisprudence. Others say it is. Some fine
debate has taken place on this issue at the ICTY – particularly in relation to
whether crimes against humanity are more serious than war crimes.
It may seem an academic issue, but it is in fact important,
particularly when the court comes to consider sentencing.
Can an international tribunal use domestic
law – can a domestic tribunal use international law?
As creatures of an international system, international
courts and tribunals only apply international law. They do gain
guidance from domestic law in certain situations but do so cautiously as the
rules cannot simply be transposed onto the international arena. The judges
of an international court therefore only look at international crimes and
yes, that reveals that international crimes are indeed regarded as a special
category of crime deserving of a special regime. But by the time we get to
this stage, the situation that led to the crimes being committed will have been
a very serious one – usually one that has led to the creation of the court as a
measure to restore international peace and security.
An examination of domestic courts trying international
crimes reveals that they do in the main examine international law and its
jurisprudence in the cases before them. But much depends on the calibre of the
judges, and there is always a tendency for them to rely on domestic concepts and
provisions as International Criminal Law is still in an evolutionary
stage. What is clear is that growing reliance is being placed on the
jurisprudence that has emerged from the ICTR and ICTY when domestic courts
process cases involving international crimes.
There are often complaints about domestic trials of such
cases being second-class justice. Sometimes, they are justified sometimes
not. Subject to how they view the particular institution (for example, the
ICTY is not seen as an independent or fair institution by a sizeable number of
persons in the Balkans), victims of atrocity would seem to prefer an
international process because they see it as a 'better' justice that
acknowledges the severity of the harm done to them. International
standards are certainly under the spotlight in an international process and I
would suggest that rights are generally well protected in the international
judicial process. If there is a domestic process, it may well be because
that is the only way that justice will be done for the victims of
atrocity. Without generalising about the standards of domestic justice,
which will vary tremendously, it often comes down to trial in the domestic
courts or nothing at all. International justice is very rare in the scale
of things and for those of us who have faith in courts of law as the first port
of call for accountability and loosing the bands of evil, the results are not
exactly impressive. How many
convictions and acquittals can the ICTY and ICTR show for all the millions of
dollars they have cost the world?
Irrespective of all the exciting developments in international
jurisprudence, have the tribunals really made a difference where they should
have - in the Balkans and Rwanda? Time will be the ultimate judge of that, but
if the empirical studies that are on the way show that they do not make a
difference, we must radically rethink how we deal with international
crimes.
Again, I would stress that that the existence of an
international body with jurisdiction does not mean the domestic jurisdiction of
the Sovereign state becomes irrelevant. The international tribunal is
usually established in situations where the State is unable or unwilling to do
anything to investigate, prosecute and punish. We are talking about
crimes that are universal in nature, that transcend the interest of any one
State. In such circumstances, the sovereign rights of States cannot and should
not take precedence over the right of the international community to act
appropriately as they affect the whole of mankind and shock the conscience of
all nations of the world. This is particularly so when an international
tribunal is established by the Security Council under its Chapter VII powers as
a response to a threat to international peace and security. A properly constituted international
tribunal could try these crimes on behalf of the international community, but
would have to take a considered decision that examines the prospects of trial in
the domestic courts, including whether this would accord with international
standards of due process and fair trial.
Searching for the truth.
Number 24. December 2001.
Magazine of Documentation Center of Cambodia (Khmer version).
INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL LAW WAS NOT INTENDED TO SUPPLANT
DOMESTIC CRIMINAL LAW
By Raymund Johansen
There has been a significant amount of commentary and
debate over the question of whether or not the criminal killings and other
crimes perpetrated under the Khmer Rouge regime are subject to prosecution as
genocide under the 1948 Genocide Convention, or as crimes against humanity
pursuant to customary international law, or both, or neither. Given the fact
that the proposed Khmer Rouge Tribunal will take place in a domestic Cambodian
court where jurisdiction over the subject crimes is not at issue, this debate
has been rendered largely academic.
Both "genocide" and "crimes against humanity" are legal
rubrics that were developed for the purpose of providing a legal basis for
jurisdiction by foreign courts, whether "international" or domestic, over crimes
that pursuant to previously unchallenged customary international law were
protected from such prosecutions under the doctrine of national sovereignty. In
the case of genocide, jurisdiction results from a nation-state’s acceptance of
the international convention that defines the crime. In the case of crimes
against humanity, an elaborate legal fiction known as the "nexus to armed
conflict" requirement was developed by the Nuremberg Tribunal to justify that
tribunal’s exercise of jurisdiction over the murder and mistreatment of German
citizens by their own government during the Nazi regime. Once a nexus was
established between those crimes (which under traditional theories of national
sovereignty were only subject to prosecution by a duly constituted German court)
and war crimes committed by the Nazis in their wars of aggression, the Nuremberg
Tribunal concluded that it would then have an adequate legal basis for extending
its jurisdiction to cover them.
The raison d’etre of both genocide and crimes against
humanity is the need to establish jurisdiction over the criminal acts
sought to be prosecuted. With possible minor exceptions, neither classification
made or makes illegal any acts that were or are not already illegal under the
laws of every civilized nation. The problem being addressed by both legal
rubrics is the lack of political will or ability on the part of a nation-state
to provide justice for massive human rights abuses perpetrated within its
jurisdiction (or by its citizens within another jurisdiction). In the case of
the proposed Khmer Rouge Tribunal, none of these jurisdictional concerns will be
at issue. The Tribunal will be a Cambodian trial of those who perpetrated crimes
in Cambodia.
As evidence of the fact that these international crimes
were never intended to be applied on the domestic level, one can note the
absurdity of denying jurisdiction to a domestic, national tribunal over crimes
against humanity committed within its jurisdiction on the grounds that those
crimes were not perpetrated in connection with an international armed conflict.
The only reason this "nexus" requirement for prosecuting crimes against humanity
evolved was in response to the need to establish a basis for jurisdiction by an
international tribunal. That it can result in denying jurisdiction to the courts
of the nation-state where the offenses took place highlights the inapplicability
of such international crimes to domestic tribunals, where the underlying
criminal acts in question are already illegal. (In any event, it can be noted
that pursuant to the enabling law for the Khmer Rouge Tribunal, the
extraordinary chambers is granted jurisdiction over all crimes against humanity
committed in Cambodia during the subject period. Since the nexus requirement
related solely to jurisdiction, and did not constitute a substantive element of
crimes against humanity as set forth at Nuremberg, the requirement has no
applicability to this domestic tribunal, whether or not it remained in effect at
the time.)
The fact that crimes against humanity and genocide were
included in the enabling legislation for the Khmer Rouge Tribunal is probably
the result of two factors: 1) previous expectations that the Tribunal would be
an international one held outside of Cambodian jurisdiction, which scenario
would then have necessitated the application of these international crimes in
order to establish jurisdiction; and 2) the unfortunate idea, promulgated by
many scholars and legal experts, that these particular categories of mass murder
are by definition more heinous than others. (While the applicable ten-year
statute of limitations under the 1956 Cambodian Penal Code may have provided
additional impetus to including these international crimes in the enabling
legislation, the law’s extension of that limitations period has addressed this
problem.)
In deference to national sovereignty, it was necessary to
limit the degree to which extra-territorial personal jurisdiction can be
exercised in criminal cases. An unfortunate if entirely predictable result was
that those criminal categories considered monstrous enough to permit derogation
of national sovereignty were defined in politically and legally circumscribed
ways. As a result, unless a particular incidence of mass murder fits within
these definitions, its victims are left feeling that they are receiving
second-rate justice. The highly abstracted debates concerning whether or not a
particular example of organized, mass murder qualifies as genocide or crimes
against humanity, understandable as they are from a legal perspective, have not
been helpful in this regard. This hyper-intellectualization has in part resulted
from the fact that the above-noted raison d’etre for genocide and crimes
against humanity has been lost sight of. The fact that the international
community found it necessary to limit the reach of these legal rubrics for
political reasons should never have been given the importance it is has by legal
scholars and commentators, attended as this has been by the uninformed parroting
of the press. That the massive human rights abuses perpetrated under Democratic
Kampuchea may not fit within the definitional restrictions of one or both of
these international crimes is a result of international political expediency,
and has no bearing upon their level of moral depravity, which was on a par with
the worst imaginable cases that would legally qualify as genocide or crimes
against humanity.
It is submitted that in the case of the proposed Khmer
Rouge Tribunal, domestic Cambodian substantive criminal law in force at the time
the crimes were committed will be entirely sufficient to provide a judicial
reckoning for the architects of what has come to be known as the "Cambodian
Genocide". Furthermore, it will be entirely fitting and appropriate that the
responsible parties be tried pursuant to the very law that they so brazenly
flouted. For those who insist on granting genocide and crimes against humanity a
higher level of heinousness than other examples of mass murder that can, and
have been imagined, I suggest that they are doing more harm than good. As others
have pointed out, in the ideal world that we are working towards there will no
longer exist any political powers, governments or entities that will ever again
take it upon themselves to so heinously oppress and abuse that portion of
humanity subject to their power. Undoubtedly progress towards this ideal state
of affairs has been accelerated through the exercise of extra-territorial
criminal jurisdiction over matters previously consigned to the domain of
national sovereignty. But the reliance upon international jurisdiction and its
substantive criminal law is in no way superior to the administration of justice
through the application of domestic criminal law, in a venue where those in
charge of the proceedings are responsible to the people who suffered from the
criminal acts in question. In short, these international crimes were neither
designed nor intended to supplant the primacy of domestic law in a duly
constituted national tribunal. Rather, they were intended to act as a stop-gap
measure where the necessary political will to punish massive human rights
atrocities is found lacking on the domestic level.
Unfortunately, there are some in the international legal
and human rights fields who seem intent on seeing precisely the opposite turn of
events, where jurisdiction over massive human rights atrocities will
increasingly and routinely be granted to an international legal bureaucracy with
no connection to the events in question and no responsibility to those affected
by them. Thus we have heard proclamations stating that the recent events at the
World Trade Center in New York City constituted "crimes against humanity" that
need to be prosecuted on an international, and thus presumably more
authoritative level. I believe that I speak for the vast majority of New Yorkers
when I insist that the only proper legal venue for the ringleaders of this
criminal enterprise will be New York, where they will be prosecuted for 5,000+
counts of plain, old-fashioned murder.
While the Rome Statute establishing the International
Criminal Court notes that the Court is being created to address situations where
the governments of nation-states where massive human rights abuses occur are
either unwilling or unable to prosecute the crimes in question, it is
interesting to note how quickly this underlying rationale seems to be getting
lost sight of. Now we are hearing calls for international prosecutions that seem
to be aimed at preventing nation-states from prosecuting offenses committed
within their jurisdictions. No doubt some of the Court’s supporters are starting
to realize that countries unwilling to prosecute massive human rights abuses
perpetrated within their jurisdictions are also likely to be unwilling to
deliver the suspects to the ICC. As a result we are already hearing proposals
for extending ICC jurisdiction far beyond its stated purpose.
It is interesting to note the Cambodian government’s
enthusiastic support for the ICC. Does anyone think for a moment that that
government would have handed over Ieng Sary, Nuon Chea or Khieu Samphan to an
ICC?
Searching for the truth. Number 23. November 2001.
Magazine of Documentation Center of Cambodia (Khmer version).
The Khmer Rouge Did Commit Genocide
By Dr. Gregory H.
Stanton
President,
Genocide Watch
The International
Campaign to End Genocide
Prof. Schabas is
wrong when he says that the Khmer Rouge did not commit genocide as it is defined
in the Genocide Convention. He is also wrong about when crimes against
humanity became defined in international law as including mass murder in
domestic settings.
Khmer Rouge
mass murder of the Cham Muslim minority was not mere assimilation, as Schabas
argues. He simply has the facts wrong. The surveys that Ben Kiernan and I
and the Cambodian Genocide Program have carried out in Cham villages showed a
mortality rate of over 50 percent, double the national average. There are also
many instances of mass murder of entire Cham villages. Over 5000 Chams
were murdered and thrown into a deep ravine on one day in Kompong Cham province
in 1977. Cham eyewitness survivors also testified to us of roundups of all
Chams in their area, followed by mass murder, including such atrocities as
burning victims alive. Besides the evidence of systematic results of mass
murder, very good proof of genocidal intent, there is also strong evidence that
destruction of the Chams was official Communist Party Central Committee policy,
including the famous edict, "The Cham shall no longer exist as a group in
Kampuchea."
Craig Etcheson
has already noted the strong evidence that the Khmer Rouge also committed
genocide against the Vietnamese ethnic group. Heder's claim that all
Vietnamese were "resident aliens" is irrelevant under the Genocide Convention.
Even if they were, they would be a national group, and destruction of them would
be genocide.
Hannum's claim
that destruction of the population of the Eastern Zone of Cambodia is also
genocide, because it is destruction in part of a national group (Cambodians),
may stretch the Genocide Convention, because it was murder of Khmers of one
region by Khmers from another region. The mass murder of the
population of the Eastern Zone was Communist Party Central Committee policy.
It was systematically carried out and members of the victim group were
marked (with blue and white checked scarves, as Ben Kiernan and I discovered in
1986) as they passed through Phnom Penh during their deportation out of the
Eastern Zone. Schabas is wrong to dismiss this as genocide simply because
it is a case of Khmers killing Khmers. To do so requires that Schabas
decide what constitutes a national or ethnic group without regard to the
ethnological view of Kampuchea as defined by the Khmer Rouge. The Khmer
Rouge defined the Eastern Zone population as ethnically different than the rest
of the population of Kampuchea: they had "Khmer bodies, but Vietnamese
heads." Definition of ethnic or national group by the perpetrators is a common
feature of genocides. The Genocide Convention does not rule it out, nor
does it say that foreign legal scholars should define what are ethnic or
national groups -- it is a matter for the court trying a case of genocide.
That is why Ratner and Abrams were right in the U.N. Commission of Inquiry
Report to leave this up to a Tribunal.
Schabas is
also wrong to say that "crimes against humanity" still required a nexus to
international armed conflict by 1979. The Nuremberg Tribunal and later UN
Resolutions stating its principles, defined crimes against humanity. But
by 1977, Optional Protocol II of the Geneva Conventions had extended the
applicability of crimes against humanity to civil conflicts, and in doing so its
framers claimed to be restating customary international law. Indeed, the acts
prohibited track closely Common Article 3 of the Geneva Conventions of 1949.
So it is legally wrong for Schabas to attempt to freeze "crimes against
humanity" from 1945 up to 1994 (when the nexus requirement to international
armed conflict was definitely no longer required in the Statute of the
International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda) or even to 1998 (the Rome Treaty of
the ICC.) Domestic mass murder and many of the other crimes of the Khmer
Rouge were already crimes against humanity during their regime.
Bill Schabas's
definitionalist denials of genocide by the Khmer Rouge and by the Yugoslav Army
in Kosovo unfortunately have pernicious effects. He means well. He would
like to limit use of the word "genocide" so that governments will act when it
really happens, and he thinks they won't act very often, so it must be very
narrowly defined ("strict construction") His view of the policy process is
naive. Governments will choose not to act even when the facts are abundantly
clear that the term genocide does apply. U.N. withdrawal from Rwanda in
1994 at the urging of genocide-denying U.S. State Department lawyers is the most
famous case. It is, in fact, a superb example of the way definitionalism
of the sort Schabas advocates can paralyze policy while lawyers wrangle over
whether the legal definition of the Genocide convention has been met. The
Human Rights Watch report on Rwanda in Spring 1994, before the genocide, which
Schabas helped write, also refused to warn of "genocide," out of fear that
it would misuse the word genocide.
Now Prof.
Schabas has been amply cited in a decision declaring that the massacres in
Kosovo did not constitute acts of genocide. His book, Genocide in
International Law, provides the basis for this finding, when Schabas argues in
effect that ethnic cleansing and genocide are mutually exclusive, because the
intent in ethnic cleansing is to drive a group out, whereas the intent in
genocide is to destroy the group. Schabas, in dividing human social acts so
neatly, ignores the obvious fact that acts of mass murder (including genocidal
acts intended to destroy part of an national, ethnic, or religious group, as
such) were committed in Kosovo in order to terrorize the population into
leaving. In other words, both genocide and ethnic cleansing were committed
in Kosovo. Schabas' denial arises out of his error in confusing motive with
legal intent. The Yugoslav motive may have been to drive Kosovars out, but
their mass murder carried ample legal intent to destroy part of the Kosovar
group. Schabas ignores the fact that multiple crimes can be committed in
the same systematic program, which in Kosovo included both acts of genocide and
ethnic cleansing.
Prof. Schabas'
genocide denial, despite (indeed, because of) his expertise, has already made a
difference in history. Prof. Schabas needs to confront the facts about the Khmer
Rouge, who did commit both genocide and crimes against humanity, as well as the
development of the law since Nuremberg. He also should recognize that
genocide and ethnic cleansing are not mutually exclusive, and that both were
committed in Cambodia Kosovo.
Searching for the truth. Number 22. October 2001.
Magazine of Documentation Center of Cambodia (Khmer version).
Should Khmer Rouge Leaders Be
Prosecutor for Genocide or Crimes Against Humanity?
By
William A. Schabas*
WERE
THE CRIMES committed by the Khmer Rouge between 1975 and W1979
"genocide"? For many years it has been common practice in human rights circles
to speak of the "Cambodian genocide". With the realistic prospect of criminal
prosecution of certain Khmer Rouge leaders finally in sight, it will become
important to determine whether in a strictly legal sense it is appropriate to
use the word "genocide".
A
strict construction of the scope of the term, defined in article II of the 1948
Convention on the Prevention and
Punishment of the Crime of Genocide[1], suggests the conclusion that the Khmer
Rouge atrocities were not genocide. According to the Convention:
In the
present Convention, genocide means any of the following acts committed with
intent to destroy, in whole or in part, a national, ethnical, racial or
religious group, as such:
(a)
Killing members of the group;
(b)
Causing serious bodily or mental harm to members of the group;
(c)
Deliberately inflicting on the group conditions of life calculated to bring
about its physical destruction in whole or in part;
(d)
Imposing measures intended to prevent births within the group;
(e)
Forcibly transferring children of the group to another group.
This
debate is not about whether the crimes committed by Pol Pot and Milosevic
actually took place; it is only about whether they are more properly described
as crimes against humanity , rather than genocide. There are several definitions
of crimes against humanity , but they share the common denominator of
persecution of individuals or groups in a widespread and systematic fashion.[2] In
the 1970s, the generally recognised definition of crimes against humanity was
derived from article VI of the Charter of the Nuremberg Tribunal: "murder,
extermination, enslavement, deportation, and other inhumane acts committed
against any civilian population, before or during the war, or persecutions on
political, racial or religious grounds".
If the
term "crimes against humanity" is more accurate, why have we tended to describe
the atrocities as "genocide". There are several reasons. First, genocide is the
most severe form of crime against humanity. Although crimes against humanity
involve terrible stigma, probably it is even worse to describe acts as genocide.
Second, the existence of the Genocide
Convention, to which Cambodia was a party at all relevant times, imposed
clear international legal obligations The same could not be said of crimes
against humanity, for which no real international treaty of universal
application existed until the adoption of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal
Court in 1998. The Rome Statute
has no retroactive application, although an argument can be made that it
largely codifies customary international law, including its definition of crimes
against humanity. Although it is now clear that crimes against humanity can be
committed in peacetime, this was not the case at Nuremberg. At some point
between 1945 and 1998 the nexus or
connection between crimes against humanity and armed conflict disappeared. But
when? Khmer Rouge defendants will argue that this took place after 1979, and
that they cannot therefore be prosecuted for crimes against humanity absent
proof of an armed conflict in Cambodia between 1975 and 1979. Genocide does not
face the same legal difficulty , because article I of the 1948 Genocide Convention specifies that the
crime can be committed "in time of peace or in time of war"
Probably aware of these legal complications associated with prosecution
for crimes against humanity , in 1979, the regime that finally chased the Khmer
Rouge from power held a show trial of Pol Pot and Ieng Sary for charges of
genocide. They were of course convicted, which is unsurprising given that
preamble of the Decree Law establishing the so-called People's Revolutionary
Tribunal denounced the massacres committed by the Pol Pot-Ieng Sary clique. The
convictions were not for genocide as defined in the 1948 Convention, but rather an idiosyncratic
definition that is substantially akin to the concept of crimes against humanity:
"planned massacres of groups of innocent people; expulsion of inhabitants of
cities and villages in order to concentrate them and force them to do hard labor
in conditions leading to their physical and mental destruction; wiping out
religion; destroying political, cultural and social structures and family and
social relations".[3]
Genocide, as defined in the Convention, requires the intentional
destruction of a "national, ethnical, racial or religious group". Which group
was it in Cambodia? The indictment at the 1979 trial talks about a "systematic
plan to kill all strata of the population".[4]
Indeed, it is generally agreed that the Khmer victims of the atrocities were
identified by social or economic standing. Those wearing eyeglasses, for
example, were singled out for persecution because they belonged to the suspect
class of intellectuals. When the definition of genocide was being devised by the
Sixth Committee of the General Assembly in 1948, there were proposals to include
social and economic groups, but these were quite unequivocally rejected.[5]
Furthermore, over the years, many have pleaded-but unsuccessfully-for an
expanded scope of the Convention so
as to cover political, economic and social groups.[6]
Hurst
Hannum and others have argued that because the victims were members of a
national group, this must constitute genocide.[7] But
the argument leads to the conclusion that all mass killing is equivalent to
genocide, because obviously any large group of people will belong to one or more
national groups. The reasoning becomes circular, tautological, and in effect
deprives the distinct concept of genocide of any real meaning. To be fair, the
argument has found some sympathy before the Spanish courts in the recent
Ponichet case[8]. The
more perverse consequences of such an argument emerged when Milosevic charged
NATO countries with genocide on the same basis before the International Court of
Justice in what is surely one of the more frivolous claims to be submitted
before that august body[9].
Most
serious observers now reject such a simplistic construction of the genocide
convention.[10] The
United Nations Group of Experts that inquired into Khmer Rouge prosecutions was
also quite sceptical of the argument. While agreeing that the Khmer people of
Cambodia constituted a national group within the meaning of the Convention, the Group said that "whether
the Khmer Rouge committed genocide with respect to part of the Khmer national
group turns on complex interpretative issues, especially concerning the Khmer
Rouge's intent with respect to its non-minority-group victims". The Group
declined taking a position on the issue, saying that the matter should be
addressed by the courts if Khmer Rouge officials are charged with genocide
against the Khmer national group[11].
Thus,
the fundamental difficulty with using the term genocide to describe the
Cambodian atrocities lies with the group that is the victim of genocide.
Destruction of Khmers by Khmers simply stretches the definition too much. At the
same time, many observers attempt to salvage the genocide allegation in Cambodia
by focusing on the persecution of religious groups, which are, of course,
comprised within the Convention
definition of genocide. The Khmer Rouge considered Buddhist monks to be social
parasites. They obliged them to abandon their religious robes and to work in
manual labor alongside the Cambodian peasants. Those who refused were punished
with great brutality. Symbols of the religion, including the pagodas, were
vandalized and pillage. The Khmer Rouge were no more tolerant toward minority
religions than they were towards Buddhism, that of the majority. Thus, for
example, the Muslim Cham were also single out for attack, with the goal being
their "assimilation" into the majority Khmer population.
Destruction of cultural institutions and forced assimilation are, of
course, very effective techniques for destroying religious or ethnic groups.
They are prohibited by international law[12].
The problem here is that these are not acts of genocide within the scope of
article II of the Convention. Indeed,
the draters of the Convention quite
expressly excluded cultural genocide, with one exception, the forced transfer of
children from group to antoher. The principal opposition to including cultural
group came from countries of the "new world", notably the United States and
Canada[13].
They wanted to stifle resistance to assimilation by immigrants and, perhaps only
intuitively at that time, were nervous about future claims from aboriginal
groups. In any event, that "cultural genocide" was excluded from the Genocide Convention is uncontestable.
For this reason, what was essentially cultural genocide perpetrated against the
Muslim Cham and the Buddhist monkhood falls short of what is proscribed by the
Convention. The treatment of the
Buddhist monks and the Muslim Cham would meet our contemporary definitions of
crimes against humanity without great difficulty[14].
And they certainly fit within the tailor-made definition of genocide adopted by
the organizers of the 1979 trial.
Nevertheless, while the term "genocide" is legally inappropriate to
describe the Khmer Rouge atrocities,
it may have irrevocably entered our human rights nomenclature. One of the
great think tanks on the subject is called the Cambodian Genocide Program, at
Yale University. Legislation enacted in the United States in 1994 declares: "The
persecution of the Cambodian people under the Khmer Rouge rule, , [when] the
bulk of the Khmer People were subjected to life in an Asian Auschwiz,
constituted one of the clearest examples of genocide in recent history."[15] A
General Assembly resolution adopted in 1997 states: "Desiring that the United Nations
respond positively to assist efforts to investigate Cambodia's tragic history
including responsibility for past international crimes, such as acts of genocide
and crimes against humanity."[16]
While
this colloquial use of the term genocide may have considerable appeal, it
becomes troublesome once criminal prosecution is contemplated, as is currently
the case with respect to the Cambodian atrocities. In the course of negotiations
concerning the establishment of a United Nations-supported Khmer Rouge tribunal,
the Cambodian government proposed to redefine genocide once again, the better to
convict[17]. A United Nations
delegation, headed by legal officer Ralph Zacklin, noted the discrepancy with
the Convention definition and charged
that any such provision would violate the prohibition of retroactive offences[18]. It added, however,
that the categories not covered by the Convention definition would be captured
under the rubric of crimes against humanity[19]. A United Nations
counter-proposal confined itself to the text of article II of the Convention[20]. This is the better
approach although it will make convictions for genocide, as opposed to crimes
against humanity, rather less likely.
* M.A. (Toronto), LL.D. (Montreal),
Professor of Human Rights Law, National University of Ireland, Galway and
Director, Irish Centre for Human Rights.
[8]
Margarita LACABE, "The Criminal Procedures against Chilean and
Argentinian Repressors in Spain",
<http://www.derechos.net/marga/papers/spain.html> (consulted Apr.
29, 1999).
[9] Legality of Use of Force (Yugoslavia
v. Belgium et al.), Verbatim Record, May
10, 1999 (Rodoljub Etinski); Legality of
Use of Force (Yugoslavia v. Belgium
et al.), Verbatim Record, May 12, 1999 (Ian Brownlie).
[11]
"Report of the Group of Experts for Cambodia
established pursuant to General Assembly resolution 52/135", U.N. Doc. A/53/850,
U.N. Doc. S/1999/231, annex, para. 65.
[14] There is, of course, the
issue of whether crimes against humanity require a nexus with armed conflict. Although
required at Nuremberg, it is today axiomatic that crimes against humanity can be
committed in time of peace. See: Prosecutor v. Tadic (Case no. IT-94-1-AR72), Decision
on the Defence Motion for Interlocutory Appeal on Jurisdiction, Oct. 2, 1995,
(1997) 105 I.L.R. 453,35 I.L.M. 32, paras. 78,140-141. Nevertheless, the point
in time at which the nexus
disappeared is certainly debatable.
[16] "Situation of human rights in Cambodia", G.A. Res.
52/135.
|
|